by Sam Waldron | Nov 15, 2019 | Apologetics
They
Just Keep Missing the Point
In my view those currently attacking Van Til and presuppositionalism are engaged in a gigantic enterprise of missing the point. They keep interpreting Romans 1:18-23 wrongly, over and over and again and again! To put it differently, they keep making the same exegetical mistake over and over again. They keep affirming that Romans 1 teaches that we can demonstrate the existence of God to men. They keep saying that men can know that God exists. But that is emphatically not what the passage says. It does not say that men can know God. It does not say that we can demonstrate to men who do not know God that God exists. It says that men do know God and that they do not need this demonstrated to them. It will probably do no good to quote the passage—since this false understanding is so deeply embedded in the thinking of Classical Apologists—, but let me do so one more time. Here is what Paul actually says: “For the wrath of God is revealed from heaven against all ungodliness and unrighteousness of men who suppress the truth in unrighteousness, 19 because that which is known about God is evident within them; for God made it evident to them. 20 For since the creation of the world His invisible attributes, His eternal power and divine nature, have been clearly seen, being understood through what has been made, so that they are without excuse. 21 For even though they knew God, they did not honor Him as God or give thanks, but they became futile in their speculations, and their foolish heart was darkened.”
Men
according to Paul not only may know God, they do know God. They know God
because they suppress the truth in unrighteousness. They know God because that which is known
about God is evident within them.
They know God because since the creation of the world His eternal power
and divine nature are clearly seen and understood. They know God because they are without
excuse. (Paul grounds their
accountability on the fact that they know God.
They are not simply potentially without excuse because they may come to
know God. They are without excuse
because they do know God.) Finally, they know God, because they sinfully
refused to honor Him or give thanks.
The
passage is clear. Men do not merely have the capability of knowing God after a
theistic proof is presented. They know
God before such a proof is presented.
Yes, this knowledge is through the things that are made, but this does
not mean that their knowledge of God is the result of a properly constructed
theistic proof. Their knowledge of God
is both mediated to them through creation and implanted in them by creation.
It
should not be surprising that his modern followers misinterpret Romans 1. They are simply following in the footsteps of
the identical mistake made by Thomas Aquinas.
Listen
to his argument in Summa Theologica Question 2, Article 2: “The Apostle
says: “The invisible things of Him are clearly seen, being understood by
the things that are made” (Rm. 1:20). But this would not be unless the
existence of God could be demonstrated through the things that are made; for
the first thing we must know of anything is whether it exists.” Thomas takes
(and the surrounding context of his assertion simply emphasizes this) Romans
1:20 to mean that the existence of God is not self-evident or implanted in man,
but can be demonstrated.
Listen
to Thomas in Summa Contra Gentiles, Chapter 12, which is entitled: “THE
OPINION OF THOSE WHO SAY THAT THE EXISTENCE OF GOD CANNOT BE DEMONSTRATED BUT
IS HELD BY FAITH ALONE.” Once more in
proving that the existence of God can be demonstrated, he brings up Romans
1:20. He says: “The falsity of this opinion is shown to us, first, from the art
of demonstration which teaches us to arrive at causes from their effects. Then,
it is shown to us from the order of the sciences. For, as it is said in the
Metaphysics [IV, 3], if there is no knowable substance higher than sensible
substance, there will be no science higher than physics. It is shown, thirdly,
from the pursuit of the philosophers, who have striven to demonstrate that God
exists. Finally, it is shown to us by the truth in the words of the Apostle
Paul: “For the invisible things of God… are clearly seen, being understood by
the things that are made” (Rom. 1:20).”
Once more, it is clear that Thomas has misunderstood Romans 1. He thinks it means that one can “arrive at”
and “demonstrate” that God exists. I
have to say it again. This is not what
Romans 1:20 teaches. It teaches men do
know God. It is not something that they “arrive at” after it has been
demonstrated to them. To echo Paul’s
argument in Romans 1:18-21, if the knowledge of God is something to be arrived
at, then their being without excuse is something to be arrived at. According to Paul, all men are without excuse
precisely because they do know God without the necessity of demonstration.
Dr. Sam Waldron is the Academic Dean of CBTS and professor of Systematic Theology. He is also one of the pastors of Grace Reformed Baptist Church in Owensboro, KY. Dr. Waldron received a B.A. from Cornerstone University, an M.Div. from Trinity Ministerial Academy, a Th.M. from Grand Rapids Theological Seminary, and a Ph.D. from Southern Baptist Theological Seminary. From 1977 to 2001 he was a pastor of the Reformed Baptist Church of Grand Rapids, MI. Dr. Waldron is the author of numerous books including A Modern Exposition of the 1689 Baptist Confession of Faith, The End Times Made Simple, Baptist Roots in America, To Be Continued?, and MacArthur’s Millennial Manifesto: A Friendly Response.
by Sam Waldron | Nov 13, 2019 | Apologetics
Aquinas’
Inadequate Views of Noetic Depravity
Van
Til and presuppositionalism object to Aquinas’s approach to natural theology
and apologetics. One major reason given for this is that Thomism exhibits an
over-confidence in fallen human reason. Does Thomas over-rate the ability of
human reason and under-rate the effects of noetic depravity (the depravity of
fallen man’s mind) in his natural theology?
I think he does, but this requires a little explanation, if we are to be
entirely fair to Thomas.
The
picture that many have of Thomas Aquinas as a typical, semi-Pelagian Roman
Catholic is certainly not correct. At key points on the doctrine of grace he
follows Augustine carefully and deserves in those respects to be regarded as a
strict Augustinian. This is, of course,
a huge problem for modern Roman Catholicism because of its clearly
semi-Pelagian tendencies.
Aquinas, in spite of
modern Thomists’ misconceptions, was thoroughly Augustinian in his view of
predestination. In his treatment of
predestination Aquinas answers a number of questions in the way that only
Augustine and his strict followers would answer. [1]
Here is a brief summary.
- “Whether Men Are Predestined by God?” Yes!
- “Whether Predestination Places Anything in the
Predestined?” No! (Men are passive in this matter.)
- “Whether God Reprobates Any Men?” Yes!
- “Whether the Predestined Are Chosen by God?” Yes!
- “Whether the Foreknowledge of Merits Is the
Cause of Predestination?” No!
- “Whether Predestination Is Certain?” Yes!
- “Whether the Number of the Predestined Is
Certain?” Yes!
- “Whether Predestination Can Be Furthered by the Prayers of the
Saints?” No, in that predestination is first determined regardless of the
prayers of the saints. Yes, in that the effect of predestination—salvation—can
be furthered by the prayers of the saints as a means of grace.
This last question and answer exactly parallels
Augustine’s argument in his book entitled, Of Rebuke and Grace (as do
all the others). Thomas echoes the anti-Pelagian teaching of Augustine.
Similarly, and not surprisingly, Thomas also
agrees with Augustine about what is now known as “irresistible grace.” Once again through his typical and very
analytical treatment Aquinas follows the course laid out by Augustine. [2] But
the pinnacle is reached when Aquinas teaches what amounts to effectual calling
or irresistible grace: “… since God’s intention cannot fail, according to the
saying of Augustine in his book on the Predestination of the Saints … that by
God’s good gifts whoever is liberated is most certainly liberated. Hence if God intends, while moving, that the
one whose heart He moves should attain to grace, he will infallibly attain to
it …”[3]
With such evidence in front of us, we may
rather expect that Aquinas will follow out what we know as the Calvinistic
scheme by teaching the perseverance and preservation of the saints and the
other doctrines of grace. Sadly, this
assumption is not the case. Neither
Augustine, his strict follower, Gottschalk, nor Thomas Aquinas affirm the
preservation of the saints. Grace may be
lost unless one is also predestined to persevere. Once more Thomas Aquinas is a good
Augustinian when he says: “Many have meritorious works who do not obtain
perseverance …” [4]
Similarly, Aquinas also seems to have held
confused and imperfect views of total depravity. Sin, in fact, does not seem to occupy an
important place in Thomas’s writings. In
Gilson’s index there is no entry for sin, depravity, the fall, or folly. For a discussion of Thomas’s view of sin, one
must consult his doctrine of free will and grace. It is not surprising, then,
Thomas argues that natural light is sufficient for natural knowledge.
Consequently, human nature is not altogether corrupted by sin. [5]
The effects of this view of human nature become
evident in Thomas’s approach to the existence of God. In several places Thomas
argues that the existence of God is not self-evident because sinful men can
conceive that God does not exist, and if something is self-evident it cannot be
conceived by anyone as not existing. He
proves this by citing “the ancients,” that is, the ancient Greek philosophers.
He also cites the fact that the fool denies the existence of God.
Surprisingly, instead of attributing such
denials to the noetic depravity of men and the fact that they suppress the
truth in unrighteousness (Rom. 1:18), Thomas takes these statements of the fool
and the ancients at face value. He then uses them as an argument against the
self-evident character of the existence of God. Nothing could more pointedly
inform us of Thomas’s inflated view of the powers of fallen human reason.
Here are the quotes from Aquinas: “And,
contrary to the Point made by the first argument, it does not follow
immediately that, as soon as we know the meaning of the name God, the existence
of God is known. It does not follow first because it is not known to all, even
including those who admit that God exists, that God is that than which a
greater cannot be thought. After all, many ancients said that this world itself
was God.” [6]
Cf. also: “On the contrary, no one can mentally admit the opposite of what is
self-evident; as the Philosopher … states concerning the first principles of
demonstration. But the opposite of the proposition “God is” can be mentally
admitted: The fool hath said in his heart, There is no God (Ps. Lii. 1). Therefore
that God exists is not self-evident.” [7]
Thus, despite the promising character of
Thomas’s views of predestination and grace, he falls short of truly
appreciating the total depravity of man including his reason. This in turn profoundly controls his approach
to apologetics and the theistic proofs. This is why Aquinas can say that the fool
and the ancients disprove the self-evident-ness of the existence of God. This
is clear evidence that Thomas indulged deficient views of human depravity.
[1] Thomas Aquinas, Summa
Theologica, Volume 1, Question 23, Articles 1-8.
[2] Summa Theologica, Volume 2,
Question 112, Articles 1-3.
[3] Summa Theologica, Volume 2,
Question 112, Articles 3.
[4] Summa Theologica, Volume 2,
Question 114, Article 9. Since the true
grace of regeneration was given through the sacrament of baptism, and it was
plain that not all the baptized persevered, no one committed to the notion of
baptismal regeneration in any sense could hold the Calvinistic view of the
perseverance of the saints.
[5] Summa Theologica, Volume 2,
Question 109, Article 2.
[6] Thomas Aquinas, Summa Contra
Gentiles, Book 1, Chapter 11, Paragraph 3
[7] Summa Theologica, Volume 1,
Question 2, Article 1
Dr. Sam Waldron is the Academic Dean of CBTS and professor of Systematic Theology. He is also one of the pastors of Grace Reformed Baptist Church in Owensboro, KY. Dr. Waldron received a B.A. from Cornerstone University, an M.Div. from Trinity Ministerial Academy, a Th.M. from Grand Rapids Theological Seminary, and a Ph.D. from Southern Baptist Theological Seminary. From 1977 to 2001 he was a pastor of the Reformed Baptist Church of Grand Rapids, MI. Dr. Waldron is the author of numerous books including A Modern Exposition of the 1689 Baptist Confession of Faith, The End Times Made Simple, Baptist Roots in America, To Be Continued?, and MacArthur’s Millennial Manifesto: A Friendly Response.
by Sam Waldron | Nov 7, 2019 | Apologetics
After
Reading Aquinas!
“Everyone”
knows that recently there has been quite a furor created by the claims of J. V.
Fesko (Reforming Apologetics—Retrieving the Classical Reformed Approach to Defending
the Faith), Keith Mathison (Christianity and Van Tillianism),
Richard Muller (Aquinas Reconsidered), and other critics of Van Til.
Their assertion is that Cornelius Van Til substantially misunderstood and/or
misrepresented Thomas Aquinas in the construction of his presuppositional
apologetics. In turn this exposes to criticism the supposed “Copernican”
revolution which presuppositionalism claimed to represent in the area of Christian
Apologetics.
As
part of my course on Apologetics for CBTS I begin with an historical
introduction to the subject. After that I delve deeply into the significance of
the major, relevant, biblical passages for Christian Apologetics and for the
major issues revealed by this historical introduction. Therefore, after lecturing on the contrast
between Justin Martyr and Tertullian in the Early Church period and before
coming to the contrast between Warfield and Kuyper in the Modern Church, I
lecture on the contrast between Aquinas and Calvin in what I call the period of
the Augustinian Church.
It
was the lecture on Aquinas that caused me concern. Of course, the contrast for which I argue between
Aquinas and Calvin is called into question by the advocates of Reformed
Scholasticism. But the bigger issue was the
propriety of the way that I (generally following Van Til’s lead) described
Aquinas’s views.
I
was encouraged, however, to see that I rarely quoted Van Til or his assessment
of Aquinas in this lecture. Rather, the
views of Gordon H. Clark, E. J. Carnell, and Kelly James Clark are much more
frequently cited. Substantially, they give the same account of Thomas Aquinas
as Van Til. Still, I felt that I was myself
too reliant on secondary sources for my description of Thomas Aquinas and not
well enough read in Thomas Aquinas to defend my treatment and description of
his “classical approach” to Apologetics. I determined to make sure that I had rectified
this before the lecture on Aquinas.
Thus, I read the relevant sections of Thomas Aquinas for myself before
giving this lecture.
I
procured and then scoured the relevant sections of his Summa Contra Gentiles
and Summa Theologica. This
reading caused considerable expansion of that lecture. It actually—in fact—expanded it into two
lectures. What it did not do, however, was significantly change my
understanding of Thomas Aquinas “Classical Apologetics” at all. I concluded that basically Van Til’s
presentation of Thomas was right.
This conclusion should not really surprise anyone. In his recent blog posts on the subject James Anderson points out that, even if Van Til was not deeply acquainted with Aquinas’ writings himself, he was at least using the exposition of Aquinas available from the premier Aquinas scholar of the 20th century. I refer to Etienne Gilson and his The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas. Here is what Anderson says: “I think it’s also fair to criticize Van Til for relying heavily on secondary sources and not engaging more directly with Aquinas’s works. Even so, Van Til engages frequently with Etienne Gilson, who was one of the leading authorities on Aquinas during Van Til’s career, so it’s not as though his secondary sources were dubious ones! If Van Til was interacting with Aquinas through the lens of Gilson and other contemporary scholars, then he was interacting with the interpretation of Aquinas that was dominant in his day.” [i] As I read Gilson, it was clear to me that his treatment was a closely accurate portrayal of Thomas Aquinas, his Christian philosophy, and his Apologetics.
In
the posts to follow I want to respond to the criticisms of presuppositionalism based
on the fascination with Aquinas among some contemporary Reformed scholars. I will point out several misguided and unhelpful
directions that are being taken in the current discussion of Aquinas and
Christian Apologetics.
[i] https://www.proginosko.com/2019/08/reforming-apologetics-thomas-aquinas/
Dr. Sam Waldron is the Academic Dean of CBTS and professor of Systematic Theology. He is also one of the pastors of Grace Reformed Baptist Church in Owensboro, KY. Dr. Waldron received a B.A. from Cornerstone University, an M.Div. from Trinity Ministerial Academy, a Th.M. from Grand Rapids Theological Seminary, and a Ph.D. from Southern Baptist Theological Seminary. From 1977 to 2001 he was a pastor of the Reformed Baptist Church of Grand Rapids, MI. Dr. Waldron is the author of numerous books including A Modern Exposition of the 1689 Baptist Confession of Faith, The End Times Made Simple, Baptist Roots in America, To Be Continued?, and MacArthur’s Millennial Manifesto: A Friendly Response.
by Sam Waldron | Jun 7, 2019 | Apologetics, Book Reviews
Part 1: Preface
Part 2 Introduction
Part 3: Overview
Evaluation
Commendation
There
is certainly much that is challenging in Fesko’s work. There is definitely much to be learned. Furthermore, given the directions Reformed
historiography has taken in recent years, it seems to me that a book like this had to be written. Let me commend a number of things in it.
First,
as I have just said, his summary of what a biblical and covenantal epistemology
looks like was well done. Presuppositionalist that I am, I still find it a very
helpful summary of the scriptural approach to how we know.
Second,
I much appreciated his account of the purposes of apologetics. Here is what he
says:
Apologetics, narrowly construed as a rational defense of Christianity, does not convert fallen sinners. … I argue that apologetics has a threefold purpose: (1) to refute intellectual objections to the Christian faith, (2) to clarify our understanding of the truth, and (3) to encourage and edify believers in their faith. (203-04)
I
think Fesko here helpfully articulates the fact that apologetics (narrowly
construed) has a negative and kind of secondary purpose. It does not and ought not to pretend to
create arguments for the existence of God which positively ground the believer’s
faith. Without pretending to understand
all that was in Fesko’s mind when he wrote this, it does suggest to me a number
of important features of the apologetic endeavor. First, apologetics is properly
defensive. It is an apologia or defense
of the faith. It is not, then, properly
(or narrowly) speaking a positive attempt to argue discursively for the
existence of God or the truth of Christianity.
It assumes the faith and defends the faith so assumed against
attack. Second, this suggests to me,
secondly, that the much disputed arguments for the existence of God appear
quite differently depending (1) on whether they are construed as the positive
ground or origin of the Christian’s faith in God or (2) whether they are
construed as defenses of a faith already assumed. I think that Bavinck and others have seen
something of this distinction when they have argued that these arguments are confirmations of or testimonies to the existence of God rather than proofs.[1] As testimonies and
properly constructed, the traditional “proofs” may have a certain defensive
value toward unbelievers and confirming value for believers. Third, it seems to
me that we may want to distinguish in our discussions of the existence of God
between apologetics more broadly considered as epistemology (how we know that
God exists) and more narrowly considered as apologetics (how we defend our
faith in the existence of God to unbelievers).
Thirdly
by way of commendation, it must be said that Fesko’s book exhibits many, fine
scholarly qualities. It manifests widely
read scholarship. It shows that he attempts to fairly represent those with whom
he differs. Though complicating his
argument, Fesko still nuances his views and especially his assessment of Van
Til. (108, 137, 141, 144)
Fourth,
I thought his account of faith seeking understanding was well said. In particular, I appreciated his statement to
the effect that “trusting authority lies at the root of all epistemology.”
(195)
Critiques
First,
from the beginning of his book till its end Fesko consistently fails to
understand the distinction between natural revelation and natural theology in
Presuppositionalism. There is no more
crucial distinction than this for Presuppositionalism in my opinion. When Van Til rejects natural theology, he is
not rejecting or giving up on the book of nature. With regard to the book of nature or natural
revelation, Van Til never tires of saying that believers and unbelievers have everything in common. The reader should consult Van Til’s essay
entitled, “Nature and Scripture,” in The
Infallible Word cited previously and his many other assertions to this
effect.[2] It simply is not true that Van Til denies the
commonality between believers and unbelievers with regard to common notions and
the like. This is, however, what Fesko
assumes everywhere. (4, 9, 12, 26, 48, 65, 68-69, 99, 100, 109, 110, 111, 114,
125, 126, 135-36, 146-147, 149, 194, 212, 219) Only if common notions are made
to consist in a natural theology created by depraved men, would Van Til oppose
such common notions. This critique
cannot be pursued without mentioning a second difficulty.
Secondly,
then, Fesko fails to weigh properly the apologetic effects of Thomas’
sub-biblical view of sin. (34, 72, 75, 78, 80, 84, 85, 94, 104) This is
important because it is exactly this factor which distinguishes Van Til’s
assessment of natural revelation from his assessment of natural theology. Natural revelation is the divine given of
human existence which at a basic level of awareness all men cannot escape. Natural theology is the human interpretation
of natural revelation. Because Van Til
holds with Reformed theology that men are totally depraved and that this
depravity affects their mind and reason radically, he cannot allow that a
natural theology can be any kind of preamble to faith. By definition such a natural theology is an
interpretive endeavor pursued by men who are totally depraved. Thus, it cannot be successful. Rather,
depraved human reason must and will inevitably corrupt the meaning of natural
revelation in any natural theology it creates.
Such a natural theology cannot serve in any sense as a preamble to
faith.
Let
me mention here that my own reading has convinced me that the categories and
terminologies with which Reformed Scholasticism discussed natural theology were
inadequate. They were inadequate
precisely because they did not clearly distinguish between natural revelation
and natural theology. Sometimes natural
theology is used by Reformed scholastics to mean natural revelation. Van Til’s apologetics pressed a distinction
between these two things that is, in my view, massively important.
This
brings up a third criticism. Unless
Fesko is willing to say that Thomas Aquinas has a fully biblical and Reformed
view of sin, and he does not seem to say this, he cannot expect Reformed
Christians to find in Aquinas a model for apologetic endeavor. Yet, clearly, Fesko offers Aquinas as a model
for Christian apologetics. (96) The whole hinge of the distinction between a
true natural revelation and a proper natural theology resides in one’s doctrine
of sin. If Thomas Aquinas’s doctrine of
sin was inadequate, then his view of natural theology cannot be correct.
Fourth,
Fesko probably depreciates Calvin’s critique of scholasticism. (52, 53, 68, 69)
It seems to me that a statistical study of Calvin’s Institutes will show that Calvin
frequently cites Augustine with enthusiasm, but rarely cites Aquinas positively
or at all.[3] Furthermore, his references to scholastic
theology are mostly critical. One does
not have to disagree with Muller’s thesis of a scholastic method in Calvin to
argue that Calvin consistently rejected their doctrinal conclusions. (53) It
remains to be seen, in my view, what Calvin’s view of Aquinas’s theology might
have been. I am not convinced that
Calvin’s statements about the existence of God which are characterized as rhetorical by Muller (64) are the same in
character as Thomas’s five proofs for the existence of God.
Fifth,
Fesko engages repeatedly in the common, evidentialist misunderstanding of key
texts of Scripture and Calvin which assert the knowledge of God. He sees in these statements warrants for
arguments for God rather than statements of the fact that men know God without
discursive arguments. (62, 63, 64, 77,
89, 90) The fact is that Romans 1:18-23 does not teach that men may come to
know God or that men may argue for the existence of God from natural
reason. This passage and similar ones
teach rather that men actually do know
God from natural revelation without the complicated and lengthy arguments
of Anselm or Aquinas. We have heard
evidentialist and post-Enlightenment classically oriented apologists make this
mistake too often to overlook it when Fesko makes precisely the same mistake.
Sixth,
Fesko’s argument for Christians not claiming comprehensive knowledge of
everything on the basis of the Bible is imbalanced. Of course, the Reformed confessional
tradition makes clear that the sufficiency of Scripture is not its
omni-sufficiency for every science. Cf.
the Westminster and 1689 at 1:6. What Fesko fails to see, however, in his
polemic against Idealism and Worldview theory is that what the Bible does teach
sufficiently is basic and foundational for every other area of study. Fesko does not clearly state that, while
Christians do not claim that the Bible is sufficient for all knowledge, they do
believe that it is basic or foundational to all knowledge and that nothing is
properly understood unless understood theistically. While unbelievers have a functional or
working knowledge of some things, they have a proper theological knowledge of
nothing. (67, 98, 99, 104, 127, 129, 209, 215, 216, 217) Sometimes Fesko seems
to notice this. He makes clear, for
instance, that Scripture truth claims do create givens for the science of human
origins and universal origins. (216) It does this, however, because scriptural
knowledge, while not sufficient for non-religious and non-theological sciences,
is foundational for them. How can what
we believe about God not be basic for
all human knowledge? Yet, Fesko can say
that the covenantal exile in which they live does not mean that “everything
they do is wrong.” (210) We know what he means, but surely what he says is not
all the truth. In another sense and in
the most important sense, everything they do is wrong. Their covenant exile does affect everything
they do. Surely if any generation of
Americans should see this, we should.
Our culture is falling apart. In
the midst of the cultural disaster all around us—with its devastating effects
on everything and even on something so basic as gender identity—shall our
message be to unbelievers that not
everything you do is wrong. They are
wrong basically and foundationally about God, and this does affect
everything. But with his concern to
counter the triumphalism of some Christians and their excessive claims, Fesko
denies the antithesis between Christianity and other worldviews and the devastating
effects of this antithesis culturally and educationally. (120, 123, 130, 133,
194, 210, 211, 215)
Conclusion
We
are glad for the emphasis of Fesko and others that there is a generally agreed
upon classical theism that resides in the scholastic tradition of the church. We agree that 21st century
Christians do not get to re-define the Christian God. The Reformation itself, however, shows that
the scholastic tradition could deviate into bypaths. It also shows that one must account for
positive doctrinal development in the church.
For myself, and I suspect others, I am not ready to return to the
natural theology of Aquinas. I find in
Calvin, in the Reformed tradition, and Van Til’s Presuppositionalism a progress
of doctrine which improves upon the natural theology of Thomism.
[1]John Frame, The Doctrine of God
(Phillipsburg, NJ: P&R Publishing,
2002), 740; Herman Bavinck, ed. John Bolt, trans. Jon Vriend, Reformed
Dogmatics First(Grand Rapids: Baker, 2004), 2:90, 91.
[2]The Infallible Word:
a Symposium, (Philipsburg,
NJ: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1978), “Nature and Scripture,” 263-301. Cf. the tract by Cornelius Van Til, Common Grace and Witness-bearing (Lewis
J. Grotenhuis, Belvedere Road, Phillipsburg, NJ), 8f. Cf. his The Defense of Christianity and My Credo
(Philipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian and Reformed, n.d.), 11: “Natural revelation is
perfectly clear. Men ought through it
to see al other things as dependent on God. But only one who looks at nature
through the mirror of Scripture does
understand natural revelation for what it is. Furthermore, no one can see
Scripture for what it is unless he is given the ability to do so by the
regenerating power of the Holy Spirit.”
Cf. also page 24 of the same tract where Van Til approvingly cites
Calvin and says: “Calvin makes a sharp distinction between the revelation of
God to man and man’s response to that revelation. This implies the rejection of a natural
theology such as Aquinas taught.” He goes on to distinguish the responses to
God’s revelation by (1) man in his original condition, (2) mankind, whose
“understanding is subjected to blindness and the heart to depravity” (3) those
that are “taught of Christ” through Scripture and whose eyes have been opened
by the Holy Spirit.” In Van Til’s syllabus entitled, “An Introduction to
Systematic Theology,” reprinted in 1966 pages 75-109 emphasize the importance
of general or natural revelation. Cf. also Greg Bahnsen, Van Til’s Apologetic (Phillipsburg, NJ: P&R Publishing, 1998),
177-194. In these pages Bahnsen
documents Van Til’s commitment to “the inescapable knowledge of God in nature”
and the distinction between natural revelation and natural theology.
[3]I did a count of Book 1 of the Institutes (McNeil-Battles edition) [John
Calvin, Institutes of the Christian
Religion ed. By John T McNeill; trans. by Ford Lewis Battles (Philadlephia:
The Westminster Press, MCMLX) to confirm for myself the evidence. Here are the results of my own count. Calvin never mentions by name Thomas
Aquinas. There is one possible and
positive reference to his writings that I found (210). Calvin mentions Plato one time positively
(46). He mentions Aristotle by name 4
times once neutrally (82) and three times negatively (56, 194, 194). Calvin, on the other hand, mentions Augustine
by name and always positively 25 times (5, 76, 77, 77, 78, 92, 105, 106, 106,
110, 113, 126, 126, 127, 143, 144, 144, 144, 158, 207, 207, 208, 213, 234, 237)
and there is an additional possible reference to Augustine but not by name
(217). Augustine is massively the most cited church father in Book 1. I think this continues throughout Books 2-4.
I would say that these statistics present an obstacle for the idea of a
Thomistic Calvin.
Dr. Sam Waldron is the Academic Dean of CBTS and professor of Systematic Theology. He is also one of the pastors of Grace Reformed Baptist Church in Owensboro, KY. Dr. Waldron received a B.A. from Cornerstone University, an M.Div. from Trinity Ministerial Academy, a Th.M. from Grand Rapids Theological Seminary, and a Ph.D. from Southern Baptist Theological Seminary. From 1977 to 2001 he was a pastor of the Reformed Baptist Church of Grand Rapids, MI. Dr. Waldron is the author of numerous books including A Modern Exposition of the 1689 Baptist Confession of Faith, The End Times Made Simple, Baptist Roots in America, To Be Continued?, and MacArthur’s Millennial Manifesto: A Friendly Response.
by Sam Waldron | Jun 6, 2019 | Apologetics, Book Reviews
part 1 , part 2
Overview
Reforming Apologetics consists of an
introduction and eight chapters. The
introduction provides a survey of the book with the intention of summarizing
its argument.
The
first three chapters have for their purpose the rehabilitation of natural
theology. Fesko argues in Chapter 1
which is entitled, “The Light of Nature,” that natural theology has played a
vital role in high Reformed theology or Reformed Scholasticism. Utilizing Burgess’s lectures on the light of
nature (24), he rebuts scholarly views of a previous generation that Reformed
theology was opposed to natural theology and argues that the Reformed were one
with the “common catholic heritage” found in Aquinas and Augustine which
affirmed natural theology (25-26).
In
Chapter 2 Fesko discusses the idea of common notions. Once more from Anthony Burgess’s lectures on
the law he shows that “common notions” were a part of the theology of the
Puritans. He proceeds to argue that “common notions” were taught by the Greek
philosophers and were “the proximate source” of the concept in high Reformed
theology. (32) Once more Fesko concludes
that Reformed theology held a form of natural theology. (48)
In
Chapter 3 Fesko specifically addresses “Calvin.” That is the title of the chapter. Calvin’s views must be discussed because Calvin
is frequently seen as the opponent of natural theology. Fesko associates Van
Til with Barth’s famous rejection of natural theology. (51-52) This leads Fesko
to reiterate some of Richard Muller’s work showing that Calvin utilized a
scholastic methodology, though not so overtly as some later Reformed
theologians. He is careful to
distinguish between the use of this methodology and “specific doctrinal
outcomes.” (54) Nevertheless, Fesko argues that the traditional arguments for
the existence of God are implicit in Calvin’s writing. (63-65) Thus, he once
more concludes that Calvin held and taught a form of natural theology in
continuity with the catholic tradition. (68-69)
In
Chapters 4-7 Fesko turns to several specific issues raised by his claim that natural
theology is part and parcel of the Reformed tradition beginning with Calvin
himself.
Chapter
4 is simply entitled, “Thomas Aquinas.”
Fesko’s treatment of Van Til and Aquinas is strangely both blunt and
nuanced. Early in the chapter with
reference to Van Til’s critique of Aquinas—a critique that is basic to his
apologetic project— Fesko asserts: “Is Van Til’s critique accurate? The short
answer is no.” (72) Specifically, with reference to Aquinas’ five proofs for
the existence of God, Fesko argues that Van Til has wrongly characterized
Thomas as rationalistic. (75-80)
Obviously, this is an important point to which we must return in the evaluation
of Fesko’s arguments. But at this point
Fesko attempts to explain why Van Til has misread Thomas. Fesko’s interesting explanation for this is
threefold. “There are three chief
reasons: (1) reading Thomas in the light of postmedieval developments,
particularly a post-enlightenment reading; (2) trying to divide Aquinas the
philosopher from Aquinas the theologian; and (3) failing, ultimately, to
examine clearly the primary sources.” (81)
These are serious criticisms of Van Til.
Fesko, however, attempts to soften the blow for his Van Tillian
readers. He avers: “Just because Van Til
misread Aquinas does not mean that we must embrace everything that Thomas said.
Conversely, it does not mean that everything that Van Til said on these matters
is categorically wrong. Rather, the truth lies somewhere in the middle.”
(93) In another place he remarks: “Although he erroneously evaluated Aquinas’s
views, this does not invalidate all of Van Til’s insights about the problematic
nature of autonomous reason.” (95) In spite of these concessions,
Presuppositionalists are treated with this hair-raising assessment in the very
last sentences of this chapter: “Aquinas and other theologians of the Middle
Ages and patristic period belong equally to Protestants. They have insights to offer, and we have much
to learn from them regarding theology and, perhaps especially, apologetics.”
(96)
In Chapter
5 which is simply entitled, “Worldview,” Fesko provides us one of the more
unique subjects and viewpoints in his book.
Startlingly, he argues that the emphasis of James Orr, Abraham Kuyper,
and Cornelius Van Til on the idea that one’s worldview controls how one thinks
about everything is mistaken. It is, he
affirms, a mistaken viewpoint owing to the adoption of Idealist
perspectives. This contradicts,
according to Fesko, the idea of “common notions” for which he has been at such
pains to defend in his earlier chapters.
Here we see an attempt (typical of Westminster West) to resist the
claims of some Presuppositionalists, especially those of a Theonomic bent, to
make the Scriptures speak to everything in the world. With Van Drunen and others Fesko is
interested in reserving a place for natural law and showing that the Scriptures
are intended to have a limited range of authority to matters of religion and
Christian duty. One of the more
controversial claims of Fesko in this chapter is that Moses is dependent in his
exposition of the civil law of Israel either on the Code of Hammurabi or on
material that predates that code. (121-122) I find myself deeply ambivalent
about Fesko’s view in this interesting chapter.
Once more it needs discussion in the evaluative section of this review.
Chapter
6 treats “Transcendental Arguments.”
Once more Fesko seeks to bring Van Til and Apologetics back to the
touchstone of natural theology as taught by the Reformed Scholastics. He begins by citing Turretin who affirms a
natural theology partly innate and derived from common notions and partly
acquired by being drawn from the book of nature by discursive reasoning.
(135-136) This is one of the more difficult chapters in Fesko’s book because of
the fairly constant necessity of qualifying his critique of Van Til. He cannot say that the transcendental
argument is wrong. He acknowledges it to be a useful tool. (137) He cannot quite say that Van Til rejected the
use of evidence. He must limit this claim to “some Van Tillians” and suggest
that it follows from certain statements of Van Til. (137) Perhaps the most important and consistent
claim of this chapter is that the transcendental argument is not the Copernican
Revolution in apologetics which both Van Til and Van Tillians have claimed.
(136)
The
pivotal paragraph in this chapter deserves quoting and reads as follows:
This chapter deals with three issues, namely whether (1) Van Til engages in synthetic thinking; (2) some overemphasize the coherence theory of truth at the expense of the correspondence theory; and (3) the TAG is wedded to outdated philosophical trends. Van Til accused Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) of employing synthetic thinking, combining pagan and Christian thought in order to defend the faith. But although Van Til rejected Aquinas’s methodology, in truth his own TAG is similar. Both Aquinas and Van Til employed the dominant philosophies of their day in order to build an intellectual bridge to unbelievers; Aquinas and Van Til spoke with Aristotelian and Kantian accents, respectively. (137-138)
This
is a challenging chapter for Presuppositionalists. It exposes tensions on issues like the use of
evidence and the claims made for the TAG between Van Tillians (140-141);
between Knudsen and Van Til; (144) and between Van Til’s two main interpreters
Frame and Bahnsen. (136-137) The exposure
of such divergences is serious for Presuppositionalism. It certainly raises
interesting and important issues that require resolution. At the same time the
penetrating power of this chapter’s critique is limited by the fact that on
these issues Presuppositionalism is a moving target. Or perhaps it would be
better to say that it presents several different targets!
Chapter
7, “Dualisms,” is of less interest to this reviewer. The reason is, as Fesko himself says, “This
chapter … primarily interacts with the claims of Herman Dooyeweerd.” (8) The
link here with Van Til and mainstream Presuppositionalism is tenuous. Still Fesko
seeks to make the connection through the association of Van Til with Dutch
Neo-Calvinism (161-164). At any rate,
this chapter is of less significance to me because Dooyeweerd and his
philosophy is only distantly related to Van Til, difficult to the point of incomprehensibility,
and criticized by Cornelius Van Til himself.
Fesko
reaches the conclusion of his volume in Chapter 8, “The Book of Nature and
Apologetics.” Reading this chapter was
an unusual experience. I began the
chapter saying “yes, yes, and yes.” (195-206) I closed my reading of it by
saying “no, no, and no.” (206-219) How
and why did my response change so drastically?
I think the reason is that in the first part of the chapter Fesko simply
expounds the nature and the contours of a biblical and covenantal epistemology,
but in the second he critiques Presuppositionalism.
The
exposition of what Fesko calls “starting point, the necessary commitments for a
biblical apologetic methodology” and “the nature of epistemology … within the
framework of classic covenant theology: the covenants of redemption, works, and
grace” and “the two goals of a covenant epistemology, namely, love and
eschatology” is one of the best parts of the book. (194) I worried a little
about how closely Fesko related the covenant to creation. I believe there is an important and
confessional distinction between creation and the covenant. Cf. the Westminster
Confession of Faith chapter 7, paragraph 1.
The covenant was technically an addition to creation, but I can live
with Fesko’s statement of this because teleologically creation was for the
covenant and intended as the theatre of special revelation (as Calvin avers).
Fesko
began to lose and frustrate me when he began to critique Van Til and
Presuppositionalism on the basis of this epistemology. Once more I felt that there was a drastic misunderstanding
of Presuppositionalism in play here.
Fesko clearly has Presuppositionalism and Van Til in mind when he says,
“Apologetically, this means that believers can present the gospel in
conjunction with rational arguments and evidence and know that believers can
intellectually receive and comprehend the message.” (212) Whoever thought otherwise? Certainly not Van Til who teaches that
unbelievers “get it” very well!
The most depraved of men cannot wholly escape the voice of God. Their greatest wickedness is meaningless except upon the assumption that they have sinned against the authority of God. Thoughts and deeds of utmost perversity are themselves revelational, that is, in their very abnormality. The natural man accuses or else excuses himself only because his own utterly depraved consciousness continues to point back to the original natural state of affairs. The prodigal son can never forget the father’s voice. It is the albatross forever about his neck.[1]
But
on this point this review must next turn to an evaluation of Fesko’s important
book.
[1]The Infallible Word (Philipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian and
Reformed, 1978) Cornelius Van Til, “Nature and Scripture,” 274-75.
Dr. Sam Waldron is the Academic Dean of CBTS and professor of Systematic Theology. He is also one of the pastors of Grace Reformed Baptist Church in Owensboro, KY. Dr. Waldron received a B.A. from Cornerstone University, an M.Div. from Trinity Ministerial Academy, a Th.M. from Grand Rapids Theological Seminary, and a Ph.D. from Southern Baptist Theological Seminary. From 1977 to 2001 he was a pastor of the Reformed Baptist Church of Grand Rapids, MI. Dr. Waldron is the author of numerous books including A Modern Exposition of the 1689 Baptist Confession of Faith, The End Times Made Simple, Baptist Roots in America, To Be Continued?, and MacArthur’s Millennial Manifesto: A Friendly Response.